Hacking On Koopman

\input tumble

\title Defending Koopman’s logic of support.

Koopman’s logic of support is one of the most historically important formalisations of the foundations of credence, with only de Finetti’s system being a serious competitor to it at the time of its publication in 1940 [[CITE]]. Arguably it is still a plausible system all these years later. I do not intend to show in this paper that it is correct; rather, I will contribute the project of resurrecting it by tying up a loose end in an argument of Hacking’s which purports to show that Koopman’s system is defective.

Hacking says:

is one possible defect in Koopman’s logic which had better be recorded. His logic must be a trifle too strong, for it includes the principle of anti-symmetry:


$$\hboxIf h|e \le i|d, \hbox then \neg i|d \le h|e.$$

is cast on the principle if we put $e = d = $ a box contains 40 black balls and 60 green ones; a ball will shortly be drawn from the box'. Let $i = $the next ball to be drawn from the box will be black’, and let $j = $ `the next ball to be drawn from the box will be green’. I take it that e supports both i and j; without e or some other piece of evidence, there would be no support for either of those propositions, but given e, there is some support. Now i and j are contraries, so j implies ¬i. By the thesis of implication quoted earlier, it follows that e supports ¬i at least as well as j.

Hacking goes on to show that his example values of e, d, i & j, together with anti-symmetry, cause problems. But that is not the fault of anti-symmetry at all. e supports j and j deductively entails ¬i, but e doesn’t support ¬i. So Hacking’s example contains an internal inconsistency. Hence we have a problem with the values of the variables, without even mentioning anti-symmetry. It is no surprise that the problem persists when we add the principle of anti-symmetry. That anti-symmetry fails to fix the problem does not mean that it is anti-symmetry which has introduced the problem. I conclude that Hacking’s example fails to show us anything about whether we should accept anti-symmetry.

A natural question is whether the example can be changed to avoid internal inconsistency, in such a way that the fixed version supports Hacking’s view that the principle of anti-symmetry needs to be amended.

Firstly, the most obvious, minimal changes to the example which avoid the internal inconsistency do not support Hacking’s view. I take it that such a minimal change is …

How does this work out in Bayesian language? It depends on the priors for i and j.